originally published on CounterPunch
It is hardly a coincidence that the Declaration of Independence, Adam Smith's Wealth of Nations, and Johann Friedrich Blumenbach's On the Natural Variety of Mankind were
all published within a year of one another, for each supports a
necessary aspect of a larger, integrated project. Not only was the
rationale for seizing political power (provided by the Declaration)
supported by Smith's popular text (which justified rule by the wealthy
business class). Because this wealth and power was contingent on
slavery, and territories seized by conquest, Blumenbach's theory that
the "Caucasian race" (a designation he coined, by the way) was the
supreme race was also instrumental in justifying and reinforcing the new
political economic order.
Prior to Blumenbach, the Swedish
scholar Carl Linnaeus' theory that there were four geographically
defined races provided the accepted taxonomical understanding of human
diversity. Among his innovations, Blumenbach not only added a fifth
race, he arranged the five in an hierarchy, placing the "Caucasian" at
the top. And even though this pseudo-scientific theory has been debunked
repeatedly over the years, by such mainstream sources as PBS no
less, the superstition of racial superiority, inferiority, and genetics
continues to influence thought. This, of course, is not to say that a
person of African origin, for instance, and a person of European origin
have no genetic differences. However, not only are there often greater
genetic variations within a so-called race than between people said to
belong to different races, what counts as a racial trait or
characteristic is completely arbitrary. Indeed, racial classifications
changed repeatedly historically according to the need to rationalize
political and economic exploitation. Consequently, while there is no
such thing as race in an anthropological sense, the concept of race does have a sociological meaning
involving socially constructed identities and differences. In addition
to Africans and Asians, for instance, the Irish were classified by the
British as a different race in order to justify maintaining Ireland as a
colony. And, in the 19th century, even the poor (that heterogeneous
class) were regarded as a distinct race in the US - as were Italians,
and others, who "became white" after World War II.
As such,
it is not only the case that poverty and race, like race and wealth,
cannot be easily disentangled. This entanglement, and the relations of
domination it implies, demonstrates that poverty is, in general, not
just a condition marked by the absence of economic power. Poverty refers
to a lack – or, more accurately, to a deprivation – of economic and
political power. Visible in high rates of incarceration, and epidemic
levels of preventable diseases, among other socially produced injuries,
in it purest form this weakness manifests as the slave. In light of
this, it is no coincidence that the term injury is not just
etymologically related but conceptually related to the notion of
injustice. And justice, if it means anything at all, requires that the
ongoing injuries of poverty be repaired. But how is a society to repair
such injuries? What must be accomplished in order to correct the deeply
entrenched and entangled injustices of the present social situation?
What type of repairs, or reparations, must be made?
The
concept of reparations, of course, requires clarification. In certain
respects the concept overlaps with the equitable notion of restitution –
according to which, if justice is to be effectuated, a party injured or
harmed by another must be made whole (repaired) by the injurer. As
Ta-Nehisi Coates has so eloquently argued,
there is no question that the African American community has been
monumentally harmed by the political and economic institutions of the
United States. In addition to more recent forms of racial discrimination
(and its obverse, racial privilege) such as redlining and blockbusting,
few industries have not benefited, directly or indirectly, from racism.
From insurance companies (such as Aetna)
who profited enormously from the institution of slavery, to industrial
and agricultural companies, not to mention banks, finance, and real
estate interests, tremendous fortunes were made – and, importantly,
continue to be enjoyed – from the systemic abuse and exploitation of
millions of people. Not only did slaves build the White House, as
Michelle Obama reminded us earlier this week; the labor of those slaves
continues to reverberate in the walls and halls of the White House, and
other structures, in the form of value (monetary, and otherwise).
Derived from an injustice, this type of enrichment is articulated in the
law by the doctrine of unjust enrichment.
Based on the ancient Roman legal maxim nemo locupletari potest aliena iactura,
the doctrine of unjust enrichment holds that when one is enriched at
another's expense a duty arises to rectify this by disbursing the
unjustly acquired enrichment. To take a standard example, if X
trespasses over Y's property every day, and saves a hundred dollars over
the course of a year because of this, X would be unjustly enriched by a
hundred dollars. Even if no concrete harm is suffered by Y, X would
have to return a hundred dollars to Y. If we apply the mainstream
doctrine of unjust enrichment, then, to the overall social situation,
there is no question that the African American community ought to be
reimbursed, and not merely for the collective injustice suffered. Those
who profited from this suffering (and continue to enjoy the wealth and
privilege derived from such suffering) should be dispossessed of their
unjustly attained advantage.
In
addition to the African American community, though, we must not neglect
to consider the fact that the fields their ancestors slaved over were
taken by force. Contrary to legally binding treaties, the conquest and
appropriation of the continent not only involved the murder of millions,
it continues to harm millions of Native Americans. Therefore, according
to the doctrine of unjust enrichment, the fortunes derived from
exploiting the continent (much of which is also currently accruing
interest) ought to also be divested from those unjustly enriched, and
returned to those unjustly deprived.
This,
however, does not satisfy a radical interpretation of the doctrine of
unjust enrichment. In spite of the fact that African Americans and
indigenous people have suffered inordinately, and continue to suffer
from poverty and other institutional harms as a result of historical
wrongs, immigrants from across the world (Ireland, Eastern, Central, and
Southern Europe, Western, Central, Southern, and Eastern Asia, and the
rest of the Americas, among other places) have suffered generations of
exploitation as well. From coal mines, to fields, to countless
sweatshops and factories, generations of people have lost limbs, lives,
and well-being producing tremendous wealth and power for a small class
of people. All of which is to say, when discussing the issue of
reparations and social justice, we must address the fact that (according
to the doctrine of unjust enrichment, at least) most people in this
society – the urban poor, the rural poor, the working class, the
shrinking middle class – deserve some form of reparation.
Because
money and property wind up spreading poverty far more than wealth,
instead of thinking about reparations as the distribution or
redistribution of money, or other commodities (which are alienable), we
should recognize that actual justice and peace requires a social
arrangement that is not regulated by the drive for profit (i.e., actual
peace requires non-exploitative social relations). Unlike the racist,
sexist, pseudo-democracy of the Founders, an actually democratic society
requires not just inalienable rights; the concrete preconditions for
the realization of these rights must be inalienable (that is, not for
sale), too. So, instead of the distribution of commodities, actual
social justice demands that the goal of reparations ought to be the
de-commodification of those conditions necessary for an actually just
society. Instead of producing conditions (such as housing, nutritious
food, water, health care, a healthy environment, education, and other
resources and conditions) necessary for the realization of an actually
just society in exchange for something else, then, (for profit), these
conditions should be produced as ends, for their own sake,
unconditionally.
Beyond
calls for the demilitarization of the police (not to mention the
abolition of the United States’ metastasizing prison system, debt
amnesty, an end to endless war, and environmental justice), actual,
concrete peace requires the righting of historical wrongs, and
reparations. Instead of redistributing property, however, which only
rearranges and reproduces injustice, actual justice (and actual
democracy, as opposed to pseudo-democracy) demands freedom from the
tyranny of property altogether - i.e., its de-commodification.
Tuesday, August 2, 2016
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment