Originally published on
CounterPunch
Though Tiberius
died, and the ancient Romans have all faded away, the empire has not.
As a political form the empire not only remains, it is still very much
alive. Just look outside at the various senates, and capitol buildings
dotting the landscape. Though Rome may have left more remnants of its
reign, however, Alexander the Great's empire may provide a better
example - not only of the empire as such, but of that which opposes and
resists it.
Beyond Hellenizing much of the world (to some degree laying the
groundwork for subsequent empires), Alexander of Macedon served as well
as a symbol of imperialist aspiration. From Pompey the Great, who
actively emulated Alexander's hairstyle and dress, to Julius Caesar and
Napoleon, the figure of Alexander exemplified (and in many respects
continues to exemplify) not only an unparalleled model of martial
excellence (as well as a warning of the hazards of decadence and
violence); Alexander symbolized the particularly imperialistic
characteristics of ambition, drive, and sovereign power - the supreme
power to command - not to mention heteronomy.
If we are willing to accept the proposition that Alexander is
symbolic of empire (of domination and heteronomy), however, it ought to
be added that the Cynic philosopher, Diogenes of Sinope, may be regarded
as the antithesis of Alexander (and, by extension, as the antithesis of
empire, heteronomy, and domination as well). For while Alexander may be
regarded as a singular manifestation of coercive power - as military
force - Diogenes, aside from his own self, commanded nothing. Owning
nothing and according to legend living in an upturned tub, as opposed to
the grandeur of Alexander, Diogenes championed the simple life.
Moreover, contrary to the coercive, dominating power of Alexander,
Diogenes may be said to manifest a non-coercive, emancipatory power -
the power to control oneself. Autonomous as opposed to exposed to
heteronomy, Diogenes was able to exert influence through reasoning,
without dominating or harming (although he did not entirely abstain from
harassing) others.
According to various sources, including the historian
Plutarch, Alexander and Diogenes even met. While Alexander was still a
prince he visited Corinth and sought the company of the famous
philosopher. When Alexander told the latter that he would grant the
philosopher anything he'd like, in a demonstration of audacity the Cynic
famously replied that he would like Alexander to move, as the prince
was blocking his sun. As the contemporary philosopher Peter Sloterdijk
remarks in his
Critique of Cynical Reason, this encounter
demonstrates, among other things, the "sovereign spirit" of the
philosopher. Inhabiting not a truer world, but a truer life, the
critical thinker is (to some degree) free from intimidation and
coercion. Beyond the sovereign power of Alexander, which requires
subjects to dominate and lord over, Diogenes was strikingly autonomous.
The opposition between Alexander and Diogenes, heteronomy and
autonomy, becomes even more pronounced when one considers Diogenes'
legendary response to a question concerning his citizenship. Asked from
where he came, Diogenes reputedly replied: I am a cosmopolite - a
citizen of the cosmos. In addition to putatively coining the term
cosmopolitan, Diogenes to some degree defines the notion of the
cosmopolitan - as that which, among other qualities, stands opposed to
the heteronomous logic of empire, not to mention the nation-state. For
what, after all, is the nation-state, in the end, but the manifestation
of the imperial logic on a less extensive scale? Both operate according
to the same principle - sovereignty over a territory and over a
population - Alexander's coercive power, as opposed to the non-coercive
power of Diogenes. Indeed, whereas the imperialist and/or nationalist
adheres to an ultimately anti-egalitarian ideology rooted in
force/coercion, the cosmopolitan may be said to eschew national or
imperial myths and justifications of power in favor of a skeptical,
flexible, critical thought - one that embraces difference, yet
recognizes the invariable, universal human qualities and vulnerabilities
(e.g., our common need for water, among other vital resources) that
supersede national, ethnic differences. Because the cosmopolitan is said
to be a "citizen" or member of the cosmos, or universe, it is entirely
consistent that the cosmopolitan should not only recognize but
prioritize the universal among all creatures.
Insofar as it relates to cosmopolitanism, it is worth noting
that, like other diasporic communities (which have been, usually
violently, dispersed across the world), the Jewish people, historically
at least, have been regarded as particularly cosmopolitan. To some
degree this characterization (as it generalizes an entire community) is a
stereotype. However, because marginalized communities exist in relation
to, and in contrast with, a mainstream, hegemonic culture, greater
opportunities often do arise for a relativistic, cosmopolitan outlook to
develop among marginalized communities. We see this consistently, with
all sorts of marginalized, excluded communities. And it is worth
consideration that cosmopolitan Jews (like Spinoza, and more recently
Einstein, Walter Benjamin, Jacques Derrida, and Judith Butler, among
others) tend to reject nationalistic politics. The ongoing emigration of
the more egalitarian-minded Jews from Israel only affirms this. The
cosmopolitan, anti-imperialistic, anti-nationalistic Jew is as opposed
to the logic of empire and heteronomy as the nationalistic Jew (the
Zionist - who is just as often also an imperialist) is opposed to a
meaningful cosmopolitanism - a cosmopolitanism, and supra-nationalism,
that, in the end, is the way toward a meaningful peace. For, rather than
the violence of force or command (of sovereignty), the cosmopolitan
position may be said to reflect Emmanuel Levinas' notion of care and
responsibility toward the Other - a responsibility that, as he put it,
"is an act of anarchic right that exists as outside the state."
In light of the above, the solution to the
unconscionable violence in Gaza and beyond can neither be a one-state
nor a two-state solution. Rather, actual peace requires a no state
solution. For what is the state (what is this machine designed to
exercise sovereignty over a territory and over a population) but an
instrument of war? And because the state is an instrument designed to
fight wars - both interstate wars (with other, rival states) and
intra-state wars (class and civil wars), actual peace can never arrive
in the guise of the state.
If an actual, supranational, cosmopolitan peace is to manifest
in the world, not only must the state be dismantled; peace requires not
just (as Kant expressed it in his essay
Perpetual Peace) the
total abolition of standing armies. Actual peace requires the provision
of concrete, objective conditions as well (the material preconditions
for concrete peace, such as nutritious food, water, housing, leisure,
health care, a healthy environment, among other conditions necessary for
human flourishing, not in exchange for money, but unconditionally -
that is, these conditions must be as inalienable as the political rights
they subtend). These conditions, however, are objectively precluded by
the institutions of the contemporary state (e.g., militaries, banks, and
real property, among others).
Accordingly, the state as a political form must be superseded.
To propose that the State of Israel must be destroyed, then, should not
be construed in the nationalistic sense that merely the State of Israel
must be destroyed, or superseded. If actual, concrete peace is to
manifest in the world, all states (not communities, or people, but the
agglomeration of institutions - such as borders, and war machines - that
comprise the state) must be destroyed. This should in no way be
understood to mean that only states need to be destroyed, or that
communities should be harmed, or that governments should be destroyed.
Governments and states, it is important to note, are distinct entities.
While the latter manifest sovereignty and heteronomy, and perpetuate
monumental harms, the former carry the potential to manifest autonomy in
the form of self-government - the democratic ideal par excellence.